The title of this blog
is purposefully wrong, or at least misleading. The humanities and science are not at war and are equally
important for my understanding of the world. However, as we saw in Part I many foolishly regard science
as reflecting objective truth and religion as reflecting dogma and
authority. And yet Stanley Fish
has convinced me that both these two approaches are provisional and affected by
the assumptions, beliefs, and theories of those who practice their respective
disciplines. (http://ow.ly/bNc0D) (http://ow.ly/bNbUc)
Defenders of the
humanities claim they have no problem with science, but they do challenge the
wisdom of what they call the “parascience” or “scientism.” Neurologist Raymond
Tallis defines scientism as “the
mistaken belief that the natural sciences (physics, chemistry, biology and
their derivatives) can or will give a complete description and even explanation
of everything, including human life.” (http://ow.ly/bNOi4) Novelist Marilynne Robinson in her Dwight Harrington Terry
Foundation Lectures on Religion in the Light of Science and Philosophy at Yale
(http://ow.ly/bNPbC) attacks the parascientific approach exemplified by E. O.
Wilson’s On Human Nature:
“The
core of scientific materialism is the evolutionary epic. Let me repeat its minimum claims: that the laws of the physical sciences
are consistent with those of the biological and social sciences and can be
linked in chains of causal explanation; that life and mind have a physical
basis; that the world as we know it has evolved from earlier worlds obedient to
the same laws; and that the visible universe today is everywhere subject to
these materialist explanations.”
One way to get at the
tension between the humanities and scientism is to focus on first principles,
the subject of the Albert/Krauss conflict described in Part I. Science has replaced metaphysics in the
modern academy, but it is worth recalling the Oxford English Dictionary
definition of metaphysics:
“That
branch of speculative inquiry which treats of the first principles of things,
including such concepts as being, substance, essence, time, space, cause,
identity, etc; theoretical philosophy as the ultimate science of Being and
Knowing.”
Robinson echoes Fish
when she takes parascience to task for saying that metaphysics no longer has
utility:
“To
say there is no aspect of being that metaphysics can meaningful address is a
metaphysical statement. To say that metaphysics is a cultural phase or
misapprehension that can be put aside is also a metaphysical statement. The notion of accident does nothing to
dispel mystery, nothing to diminish scale.” (http://ow.ly/bNPbC)
Robinson wants us to
remember that science is a relatively recent phenomenon culturally localized in
the West and that religion is far more ancient and global. She argues for including insights from
both in our understanding of the world, and she worries that “mind as felt
experience has been excluded from important fields of modern thought.” She finds the parascience view of human
history “to suggest a parochialism that follows from a belief in science as a
kind of magic, as if it existed apart from history and culture, rather than
being, in objective truth and inevitably, their product.” (http://ow.ly/bNPbC)
This is an observation, which I believe Fish would endorse.
Exhibiting a confidence
and ego to match Dawkins (which is saying a lot), Tallis attacks scientism with
a zeal hard to describe. His
passion seems to come from his stance as a meliorist who needs to believe that
humans are fundamentally different from other animals and that we humans have a
duty to work together to improve the conditions of existence for our fellow
man. For Tallis the stakes in this
battle are indeed high and worth fighting for; if his enemies win:
“Our
distinctive nature, our freedom, our selfhood and even human society would be
reduced to the properties of living matter, and this in turn would be ripe to
be reduced, via molecular biology, to matter period.” (http://ow.ly/bNOi4)
In a previous blog post,
I have summarized how Tallis the neurologist gleefully attacks those who have
ruined neuroscience with imaging studies that are poorly designed and
misinterpreted by the lay press. In just one example he quotes Matthew
Crawford’s characterization of a brain scan as “’a fast-acting solvent of
critical faculties.’” (http://ow.ly/bNVE5)
In numbing detail,
Tallis puts forth his thesis that much of parascience is based on overreaching
conclusions from experiments that “grotesquely simplify human life.” Tallis approvingly quotes Andrew Scull
who writes:
“The
neuroscientific findings that are so proudly proffered reflect simple simulated
experiments that in no way capture the intricacies of everyday social
situations, let alone the complex interactions over time that make up human
history.” (http://ow.ly/bNOi4)
Like Robinson, Tallis
cannot accept parascience’s insistence that everything humans do directly or
indirectly serves the replication of our selfish genes. Tallis believes such a conclusion ignores
much that is central to human nature and quotes William James to support his
case:
“Man’s
chief difference from the brutes lies in the exuberant excess of his subjective
propensities…Had his whole life not been a quest for the superfluous, he would
never have established himself as inexpugnably as he has done in the
necessary.” (http://ow.ly/bNOi4)
Although Tallis dissects
neuro-economics, neuro-law,
neuro-lit-crit, neuro-theology, neuro-truistics, neuroaesthetics, and
neuroarthistory, I will only summarize his views on art in this blog post. The parascience approach to art is
described concisely by Robinson:
“What
is art? It is a means of attracting mates, even though artists may have felt
that it was an exploration of experience, of the possibilities of
communication, and of the extraordinary collaboration of eye and hand.” (http://ow.ly/bNPbC)
Talllis disapprovingly
examines Semir Zeki who directs an institute at University College London
devoted to neuroaesthetics. Zeki
discusses his views on art.
“The
artist in a sense is a neuroscientist, exploring the potential and capacities
of the brain, though with different tools. How such creations can arouse aesthetic experiences can only
be fully understood in neural terms.
Such an understanding is now well within our reach.” (http://ow.ly/bNOi4)
Zeki believes Mondrian
speaks preferentially to cells in region V1 and V4 and that the Fauves stimulate
V4 and the middle frontal convolutions.
Tallis attacks this approach because
·
“Great
artists are more often biological losers than they are alpha semen spreaders.”
·
Art engages
us as whole human beings.
·
“Works of
art…are in dialogue with the world in which they are produced, with other works
in the same and different genres and with the earlier and later works of the
same artist. They invite us not
only to have experiences but to examine those experiences.”
·
“Rembrandt’s
series of self portraits is not merely a parade of coloured surfaces but a
profound meditation on the tragedy and beauty of the course of life.” (http://ow.ly/bNOi4)
Fish, Robinson, and
Tallis have convinced me that science does not give a complete description and
explanation of human life. I am
going to have to reject Francis
Crick’s Astonishing Hypothesis:
“You,
your joys and sorrows, your memories and your ambitions, your sense of personal
identity and free will, are in fact no more than the behavior of a vast
assembly of nerve cells and their associated molecules.” (http://ow.ly/bNVE5)
Instead I am going to embrace
Marilynne Robinson’s conclusion that there is a mind separate from the brain, there
are things unknowable in this world, and that the humanities can still teach me
things that science cannot explain:
“As
proof of the existence of mind we have only history and civilization, art,
science, and philosophy. And at the same time, of course, that extraordinary
individuation.” (http://ow.ly/bNPbC)
Did you know you can create short urls with LinkShrink and earn money for every click on your short links.
ReplyDelete